The Bayesian algorithm at Amazon recommended David Graeber’s book,
Debt:
The First 5,000 Years with the product description
Economic history states that money replaced a bartering system,
yet there isn’t any evidence to support this axiom. Anthropologist
Graeber presents a stunning reversal of this conventional wisdom.
For more than 5,000 years humans have used elaborate credit
systems to buy and sell goods. Since the beginning of the agrarian
empires, humans have been divided into debtors and creditors.
Through time, virtual credit money was replaced by gold and the
system as a whole went into decline. This fascinating history is
told for the first time.
I tell my students, almost exclusively looking towards careers in banking or
insurance, that they should take some interest in the “nature of money”, given
this is the central topic of their current studies and future careers. Practising what I
preach I thought I would get Graeber’s book.
The claim that “This fascinating history is told for the first time.” is
publicist’s hyperbole. Within economics there has always been a debate as
to the nature of money. Nicole Oresme wrote a
Treatise on the Origin,
Nature, Law, and Alterations of Money in the mid fourteenth century
and then Copernicus wrote on
On the Minting of Coin long before he
wrote on the planets. In the first decades of the nineteenth century, the
Bullionist Debates dominated British economics while the 1900 book
The
Wonderful Wizard of Oz is sometimes seen an allegory in favour of the State
Theory of Money, that money is created by governments, as opposed to the
Commodity Theory, that money is the most convenient commodity to facilitate
exchange.
In the twentieth century it was anthropologists, like Malinowski and Mauss,
who challenged the standard economic argument that money emerged out of
barter. More orthodox was John Maynard Keynes’s A Treatise on Money , motivated by the
conundrum, in the historical record, that credit existed before money. In 1985
the anthropologist Caroline Humphrey summarised the situation saying
that
Barter is at once a cornerstone of modern economic theory and
an ancient subject of debate about political justice, from Plato
and Aristotle onwards. In both discourses, which are distinct
though related, barter provides the imagined preconditions for the
emergence of money …[however] No example of a barter economy,
pure and simple, has ever been described, let alone the emergence
from it of money; all available ethnography suggests that there
never has been such a thing.
A modern narrative of this story, though not novel, would be interesting, and
Graeber’s book is full scholarship, summarising the work of other social
scientists who have addressed the basic question “what is money”. It
presents a strong case that the standard economic argument, that first
there was barter and then money emerged as a commodity to facilitate
exchange, is myth unfounded in fact. This is important since so much of
contemporary monetary policy has been based on the assumption of money as a
commodity.
The fact that Graeber castigates modern orthodox economics is important
since it sets the benchmark against which he should be measured.
In addition, there is a note referring to the novelist Margaret Atwood
[Atwood] then proceeds to explore the nature of our sense of
economic morality …Despite the brilliance of many of its arguments,
the result is a rather sad testimony to how difficult it is for the
scions of the North Atlantic professional classes not to see their
own characteristic ways of imagining the world as simple human
nature.
As a (middle class) novelist, Atwood is falling into the trap of subjective analysis,
something the scientist, even political scientists and certainly anthropologists,
should avoid.
The problem is, that when Graeber begins to consider exchange in the context
of financial markets, he relies onsimilar economic and subjective assumptions.
In the case of …commercial exchange, when both parties in the
transaction are only interested in the value of the goods transacted,
they may well – as economists insist they should – try to seek the
maximum material advantage
Given that up to this point the book has given a series of examples of when observed
behaviour does not mimic economic theory, it is striking that this one point is
made based on that same economic theory without further comment. Graeber
goes on to say
What marks commercial exchange is that it’s “impersonal”: who
it is that is selling something to us, or buying something from us,
should in principle be entirely irrelevant.
The fact is, that when sociologists and anthropologists observe the actions of
financiers, they realise that the economic theory is not, in fact, put into
practice. While the market is capable of automating trade, so that decisions
are based only on value, the markets emerged, evolved and exist on the
basis of trust between participants, an emotions centred on personal
relationships.
The sociologist Donald MacKenzie highlights this when discussing how Leo
Melamed, the chairman of the Chicago Mercantile Exchange negotiated with the
academic, Milton Friedman, about sponsoring a paper advocating the
introduction of currency futures in the early 1970s. The speculators at the Merc,
and the CBOT, were acting together in, what they believed, was the common
good, to create the market, and not in their personal interest, maximising their
wealth by focussing on competitive trading. This leads to the “delightful
paradox”, that it seemed
the very markets in which Homo economicus, the rational egoist,
appears to thrive cannot be created (if they require the solution of
collective action problems, as in Chicago) by Homo economicus.
The belief that markets are about maximising wealth, rather than creating networks, comes out of political
philosophy, emerging in early Victorian Britain with the liberal philosopher John
Stuart Mill arguing that economics
is concerned with [man] solely as a being who desires to possess
wealth, and who is capable of judging the comparative efficacy of
means for obtaining that end.
Around the same time, the poet-, Alfred, Lord Tennyson, wrote about nature
“red in tooth and claw”. In 1859 Darwin published the Origin of the
Species which explained evolution in terms of natural selection. In the
popular perception, nature became seen as being driven by a bitter struggle
for survival, un-regulated by the ethics of divine architect. It was the
leading economist at Cambridge University of the time, Alfred Marshall,
who would synthesise Mill’s approach to economics with Darwinian
metaphors
in the late nineteenth century. In the twentieth, Friedman defined ‘positive
economics’ as being disconnected from morality and his views have been
summarised as
Any deviation from that single–minded pursuit of profit–maximisation
by the admission of some other social responsibility is “fundamentally
subversive”, “pure and unadulterated socialism”, something which
could “thoroughly undermine the very foundations of our free
society.” Businessmen subjected to “a social responsibility other
than making maximum profits for stockholders” cannot know
what interests to serve.
While this is the view from broader society, it is not natural in finance. This
point is captured in a key case in the English courts in 1950,
Buttle v Saunders.
Saunders managed a trust for Buttle, and had agreed to sell a piece of land owned
by the trust for
£6,142 to a Mrs Simpson. Before the transaction had become
legally binding, another person offered the trust
£6,400 for the land. However,
Saunders believed “my word is my bond” and declined the higher offer in
favour of the original agreement with Mrs Simpson. The beneficiary of the
trust, Buttle, took Saunders to court, and the court ruled in favour of
Buttle
The only consideration which was present to [the trustees] minds
was that they had gone so far in the negotiations with Mrs
Simpson that they could not properly, from the point of view of
commercial morality, resile from those negotiations.
‘Commercial morality’ was not a valid consideration and the sale to Mrs
Simpson was declared null and English home-buyers could never again be
certain that a purchase would be completed, ‘gazumping’ had arrived,
not at the instigation of the financial adviser but on the insistence of a
judge.
The scientist Graeber has fallen into the trap that he criticises the novelist
Atwood of having succumbed to; he is imagining financiers rather than studying
them. This is significant because it means his whole thesis is based on an
assumption of what finance is about, this assumption is based on what academic economists imagine what it is about, rather than what the actual behaviour of bankers tells
us.
Googling
Graeber I discover that he is a central figure in the
“Occupy”
movement and is regarded as providing an intellectual justification for the physical
manifestation of the movement. However, I view this justification as being,
itself, based on a false axiom/assumption, and that is the assumption about the
nature of finance.
While we can acknowledge and accept the point the FCIC
makes in concluding that
there was a systemic breakdown in accountability and ethics. The
integrity of our financial markets and the public’s trust in those
markets are essential to the economic well–being of our nation.
The soundness and the sustained prosperity of the financial system
and our economy rely on the notions of fair dealing, responsibility,
and transparency.
The critical question is whether the lack of ethics the FCIC report is endogenous to
the markets, and possibly incompatible with them, as an Occupy protester may argue, or whether the natural ethics
of the market have been expunged by a series of commentators external to the
markets, from Mill to Friedman. The point is, coming to this question
with anarcho-communist preconceptions is not going to help a serious
analysis.
That said, Graeber does acknowledge that finance has not always been as it is
now. He remarks that the Medieval understanding of finace was concerned with
maintaining social relations. This leads me to suggest that there is a blind-spot for
many of the commentators on finance, and that is in regard to the problem of
randomness.
Mill, Marx, Darwin and Dickens were all contemporaries living at
a time when science was attempting to relegate randomness, chance, to history. In
the 1830s English law criminalised most forms of gambling, the consequence was
the difficulty Melamed had in creating a foreign exchange futures contract in
1970. Marxism proved popular not with the industrial proletariat, but in
agrarian economies of Russia, China and Cuba, societies exposed to random
climatic changes.
Richard Dawkins is often heard stating that “evolution is
not a random process”. Novels of the nineteenth century repeatedly use
the device of a character being ruined by reckless speculation or feckless
gambling.
The economic theory that developed at this time followed the dominant
cultural direction. Laplace had advised that mechanics should be
confined to the physical science, while the social sciences should employ
probability to manage uncertainty,
however, economists ignored this advice and built their science on
deterministic mechanics.
The point is, earlier generations had accepted chance as an integral part of life,
in particular economic life. Scholastic analysis of finance, which Graeber
commends, was based on a distinction between what would happen with certainty
and what was subject to
chance. The pioneers of mathematical probability, Pascal, Fermat, Huygens and J. Bernoulli all came to the topic trying to understand finance.
Further back in time, gambling is an almost universal
feature of primitive society. For the Greeks, the brothers Zeus, Poseidon and
Hades cast lots to divide up the universe, Zeus winning the sky, Poseidon the sea
and Hades the underworld. Hindus believe the world was a game of dice
played between Shiva and his wife, while at the heart of the epic tale of
the
Mahabharata is an, unfair, dice game between the Kauravas and the
Pandavas.
Contemporary anthropologists recognise that gambling plays a fundamental role
in contemporary neolithic communities. Consider a case observed in an Australian
aboriginal group, the Momega in a remote area of Arnhem Land around 1980.
The community had access to social security payments and there was often a
surplus left over after essentials had been bought. As the anthropologist, Jon
Altman, studying the group observed
this surplus was not equally bestowed. …This variability in bestowal
was extremely arbitrary and it resulted in inter–household variability
in access to cash.
This variability can seen as subjective discrimination of the community by the
Australian government. Gambling, according to Altman, “acted effectively to both
redistribute cash …[it] provided a means for people with no cash income to gain
cash”
and from a small stake a larger cash reserve could be generated. The random
distribution created by gambling, while not uniform, some would lose a lot,
some win a lot, was none the less objective and most people ended up
with a fair share of the cash this was important in a non-hierarchical
community because it meant that the arbitrary bestowal of money was not
corrected by another subjective distribution, such as redistribution by a
chief.
Another anthropologist, William Mitchell considered the role that
gambling plays in disrupting hierarchical social structures, such as the Indian
caste system, by studying the Wape in New Guinea around the same
time
An important task of Dumont’s classic study of Indian caste
was to demonstrate how inequality is maintained. My task is the
obverse, that is, to reveal how the Wape defeat the formidable
principle of hierarchy to maintain male equality. How do the
Wape, who, as individuals, desire wealth and who, since the 1930s,
have been directly tied to a world capitalist market system, prevent
wealth from being successfully manipulated by a few men to raise
themselves above others? The paradoxical answer is deceptively
simple: through gambling.
This is an explanation for the pervasive nature of gambling in neolithic
communities, appearing in the Vedic scriptures, potlach ceremonies of North America, and in aboriginal Australia and New Guinea and the
Hazda; it
is an objective, fair, mechanism for the redistribution of wealth.
We can criticise Graeber’s methodology and his reliance on unsupportable
assumptions, but the real failure of the Occupy movement is their inability to
appreciate the positive aspects of gambling and speculation, central to the
markets.Perhaps they should read more anthropology and less Dickens.
Notes
References
Altman, J. (1985). Gambling as a mode of redistributing and
accumulating cash among aborigines: a case study from Arnhem Land. In
Caldwell, G., Dickerson, M., Haig, B., and Sylvan, L., editors, Gambling
in Australia, pages 50–67. Croom Helm.
Backhouse, R. (1985). A History of Modern Economic Analysis.
Blackwell.
Brenner, R. and Brenner, G. A. (1990). Gambling and Speculation:
A theory, a history and a future of some human decisions. Cambridge
University Press.
FCIC (2011). The Financial Crisis Inquiry Report. Technical report,
The National Commission on the Causes of the Financial and Economic
Crisis in the United States.
Graeber, D. (2011). Debt: The first 5,000 years. Melville House.
Humphrey, C. (1985). Barter and economic disintegration. Man, 20(1).
Katz, V. J. (1993). A History of Mathematics: an Introduction. Harper
Collins.
MacKenzie, D. (2008). An Engine, Not a Camera: How Financial Models
Shape Markets. The MIT Press.
Ménard, C. (1987). Why was there no Probabilistic Revolution in economic thought? In Kruger, L., Gigerenzer, G., and Morgan, M. S.,
editors, The Probabilistic Revolution: Volume 2: Ideas in the Sciences. MIT
Press.
Mitchell, W. E. (1988). The defeat of hierarchy: Gambling as exchange
in a Sepik society. American Ethnologist, 15(4).
Persky, J. (1995). Retrospectives: The ethology of Homo economicus.
The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9(2):221–231.
Sahlins, M. (1972 (2003)). Stone Age Economics. (Routledge).
Thomas, B. (1991). Alfred Marshall on economic biology. Journal of
Financial Intermediation, 3(1):1–14.