A recent paper in economics highlights why I
think the classical operation of financial markets can inform
science, and also how modern ‘science’ hinders economics’
attempts to understand financial markets.
Underlying my interest in the specific paper is my
curiosity in the doux-commerce thesis. The thesis emerged in
the French Enlightenment as a reaction to Bourbon autocracy
stimulated by Dutch and British liberalism and is the idea is that
commerce improves society. For example, a 1704 technical text on
commerce argues “Commerce attaches [men] to one another through
mutual utility”, while in The Rights of Man (1792) Thomas
Paine writes “[Commerce] is a pacific system, operating to
cordialise mankind”. In the intervening years Montesquieu, Hume,
Condorcet and Adam Smith all agreed that commerce was a powerful
civilising agent, promoting honesty, industriousness, probity,
punctuality, and frugality, in contrast to the excesses of absolute
monarchies.
In the 1980s Albert Hirschman reviewed
the thesis and compared it to competing views that either markets
had a pernicious effect on society or that markets were shackled to
conventional morality. More recently Marion Fourcade and Kieran Healy
have reviewed the thesis from the
perspective of contemporary sociology, which generally regards
markets as ‘culture’, being embedded in society, and ‘saturated
with normativity’. In this context three themes are identified.
Developing the original doux-commerce thesis is research that
investigates the cultural context of economic concepts, such as
attitudes to insurance or gambling or how different contractual
relationships reflect different power relationships. Secondly, and of
principle interest to me, is how
the persistent tension in economics between normative and descriptive theory is shown to be resolved in practice through the development of social technologies that bring the behaviour of markets in line with the demands of theory
i.e. how contemporary financial
economics is “an engine” driving the markets and “not a camera”
observing the markets. Finally there is work looking at how
‘objective’ economics is suffused with normative (and subjective)
meaning.
In particular I am interested in Deirdre McCloskey’s
argument neatly summarised as
Commerce teaches ethics mainly through its communicative dimension, that is, by promoting conversations among equals and exchange between strangers.
because I see science as being a form
of communicative
action,
the speculative, agreed-upon inquiry which recognizes and distinguishes, defines and interprets reality and its various aspects and parts, on the basis of theoretical principles, models and methods rigorously cohering
rather than a description of ‘Truth’, which I regard
as elusive given the uncertainty of nature.
My interest in these themes emerged while preparing a penultimate
(sophmore) year course in derivative pricing I realised that the
canonical origin of mathematical probability, Fermat and Pascal’s
solution to the Problem
of Points, was formally identical to the Cox-Ross-Rubinstein
option pricing model. A fly in this Whiggish
ointment was to establish how Pascal-Fermat identified the
probabilities to be used in their model. Investigating this question
convinced
me that before 1713 the standard way of approaching probability
was in establishing ‘justice’ in exchange, and not, as is more
conventional today, as measuring relative frequencies.
Digging deeper into the origins of probability
theory I concluded
that the ethical assessment of markets was the principle driver in
the development of ‘Western science’. For me the doux-commerce
thesis is not about how markets influence morality but how the
synthesis of morality and markets creates science. This will be the
essence of the discussion as part of the
Edinburgh Fringe with David
Fergusson.
This sort of research is unusual for a modern
probabilist, and was difficult. I only did it because between
2006-2011 I was the RCUK’s
‘Academic Fellow’ in Financial Mathematics,. As such I was
expected to ‘engage’ the wider public with my research areas.
Normally the ‘public engagement’ component of the Academic
Fellowships were quietly ignored, this was difficult to me between
2007—2009. It was only because I was involved in the process of
dialogue with people not embedded in academic theory that I was able
to develop pretty unorthodox opinions (for mathematicians at least).
This work has not gone un-recognised, independent of my Fellowship
the RCUK (the UK equivalent of the National Science Foundation)
identified my ideas as one of “One
Hundred Big Ideas for the Future”.
The benefit to me of having undertaken this
research is that as well as reviewing mathematics critically I now
approach financial economics papers as political
scientist/sociologist might in that I try and discern the implicit
normative assumptions of a paper. It helps (sometimes hinders) my own
research because it provides me with a meaningful context and this
helps me identify the more important (subjective) issues my research
should focus on.
My belief is that if researchers approach the
financial markets from a Pragmatic
perspective, acknowledging both the implicit normative nature of
knowledge (which can, none the less, be objective) and the fundamental role of randomness in nature, financial
economics will improve and the methodologies of financial economics
will prove valuable for the rest of science.
Fascinating post. Now I will have to read your links. This is the main reason I hesitated to transition into academia. For an intelligent multi-disciplinary generalist, academia seems very constraining. Reinventing the wheel seems all to common. Your insights really distinguish you.
ReplyDeleteA freely available version of the paper you cited is here
ReplyDeletehttp://econweb.umd.edu/~davis/eventpapers/SimsekSpeculation.pdf