This post presents details of the argument that mathematical probability emerged between 1564 and 1713 out of the ethical analysis of commercial practice. This development of probability in the early modern period was built on foundations laid in the high Middle Ages. This piece is taken from a longer article Reciprocity as a Foundation of Financial Economics .
From
1000 C.E. until about 1300 C.E. there was a rapid development of the
economy in Western Europe as it evolved from an agriculturally based
feudal society towards a commercially based bourgeois society,
initially in Italy then, in the twelfth century, in North Western
Europe. One physical manifestation of this change was the volume of
coin circulating in the European economy, as the population doubled
over the three hundred years, the amount of coin per person tripled.
([29,
Chapter 3 & 4], [22,
pp 15–16], [25,
p 72])
Practice
Medieval
European merchants, unlike their contemporaries in the Middle East,
India or China, had to contend simultaneously with prohibitions on
usury and the heterogeneity of currency. Muslim merchants had usury
prohibitions but homogeneous currency, Indian and Chinese merchants
had to (sometimes) deal with heterogeneous currencies but without the
centralised religious prohibitions on usury.
Usury
derives from the Latin usus
meaning ‘use’,
and referred to the charging of a fee for the use of money. Interest
comes from the Latin interesse
and originated in the
Roman legal codes as the compensation paid if a contract was broken
[19,
p 73]. Shortly after 1200 the theologian, Peter the Chanter, argued
that “a buyer or seller may be excused from usury if he exposes
himself to the risk of receiving more or less” [13,
pp 263–264] and this idea that usury was absent in the presence of
risk became firmly established in the thirteenth century.
The
basic financial instrument at this time was the census that
originated when ninth century monasteries guaranteed a fixed regular
income in exchange for a donation of land. Censii developed to be
written on the back of a diverse range of assets, including a
craftsman’s labour, resembling modern day securitisation. In time
‘structured’ contracts emerged such that a borrower would receive
a lump sum secured against the future cash-flow from an asset, rente
à prix d’argent,
without necessarily relinquishing ownership of the asset ([19,
pp 75–76], [28,
pp 31–33]).
Modern
structured finance was anticipated in the triple, or German, contract
(contractus trinus),
developed to fund long distance trade. It involved a loan to fund the
venture (the first contract); the transformation of the variable
return of the venture into fixed cash-flow (the second contract); and
an insurance contract to guarantee the fixed payment (the third
contract). In terms of contemporary finance this third contract is a
Credit Default Swap and the whole contract has the same structure of
a Special Purpose Vehicle. This contract was declared illicit by the
Catholic Church in 1586 on the basis that the lender received a
risk-less return. [26,
pp 209–220]
The
heterogeneity of currency was a consequence of feudalism and the
desire of magnates to assert their authority by issuing coin. The
Italian peninsula had over twenty currencies, the Kingdom of France
three, and each prince of the Holy Roman Empire would mint their own
coin. Alfred Crosby describes the activities of a Tuscan merchant in
supplying cloth to Venice from Mallorcan wool that involved at least
five currencies [8,
p 201]. William Goetzman explains that as a consequence of the
multitude of currencies, European medieval merchants “operated in a
world of complete relativism” [14]
while Crosby remarks that there was an “abstraction of Western
merchants’ scale of value” and “no people were more obsessed
with counting and counting and counting”[8,
p 72, 74].
A
solution to the problem of the complexity of Medieval commerce came
in Fibonacci’s Liber
Abaci first published
in 1202, the initiant of Financial Economics ([8,
43–47], [32,
Introduction]). It was an immediate success and a second edition was
produced in 1228, a remarkable feat in an age when books were hand
copied [32,
p 4]. The text introduces Arabic/Hindu numerals and explains basic
arithmetic over seven chapters. It then presents four chapters
applying the theory by presenting cases on practical commercial
problems. The text finishes with a more theoretical section on
iterating to a solution of a problem. ([32],
[14])
Before
the Liber Abaci,
European merchants, like their contemporaries across the globe, would
have used an abacus to perform arithmetic calculations, and once a
calculation had been made, it was recorded. The technologies
described in the Liber
Abaci, particularly
Hindu numbers, meant that merchants could write down their
calculation method, the algorithm, which could be copied and modified
by others. Knowledge, in the form of best practice, could be created,
distributed and improved.
Abaco
or rekoning
schools sprang up
throughout Europe teaching apprentice merchants the techniques
originating the Liber
Abaci. The impact of
these abaco schools was enormous, algebra became an important tool
used by the large and influential community of Europeans and would
provide the reservoir of mathematicians on which the scientific
developments of the seventeenth century were built. The unique
circumstances of medieval European commercial practice offer a
solution to Needham’s question that asks why European technological
development accelerated so much faster than Chinese after 1600. ([16,
Chapter 1], [32,
Introduction], [18]
)
Theory
The
societal changes before 1200 led to a need to revitalise the Catholic
Church, particularly to combat unorthodoxy such as Catharism. The
Dominican and Franciscan orders were established to engage with the
emerging bourgeoisie and would come to dominate Scholasticism, the
intellectual movement that integrated Greek philosophy and Christian
theology in Europe’s universities until the Reformation.
The
science that emerged in Western Europe in the seventeenth century is
distinctive in its use of mathematics to describe the laws of nature.
The Greeks, and their Muslim successors, generally regarded ‘pure’
mathematics as being irrelevant to the sensible world while Chinese
scientists used mathematics to calculate but not to describe ([8,
p 16], [11,
p 164], [12,
p 53]). Richard Hadden, Alfred Crosby and Joel Kaye have all argued
that the ‘mathematisation’ of European science began with the
synthesis of commercial practice and Scholastic ethics in the
thirteenth and fourteenth centuries ([16],
[8],
[22]).
A key
component of this synthesis was Aristotle’s Nicomachean
Ethics that addresses
how an individual can live as part of a community and it discusses
economics in Book V in the context of the virtue of Justice.
Aristotle saw reciprocity in exchange as being important in binding
society together, and Aristotle believed exchange was performed to
correct for inequalities in endowment and to establish a social
equilibrium, not in order to generate a profit ([22,
p 51], [5,
1133a15–30]).
Aristotle
distinguishes economic justice into two classes, distributive and
directive (or corrective, restorative). Distributive justice is
concerned with the distribution of common goods by a central
authority in proportion to the recipients’ worth and is determined
by equating Geometric Proportions. Directive justice applies in cases
where the parties are considered to be equal, for example in
commerce, in which case justice is determined by equating Arithmetic
Proportion and is based on reciprocity ([22,
p 41–43], [5,
1130b30–31a5]).
What
is most striking in Aristotle’s treatment of economic exchange is
that he approached it as a mathematical problem. This is remarkable
in itself because Aristotle rarely applied mathematics to the
sensible world elsewhere ([16,
p 75], [8,
p 13], [5,
1094b15–28]). Aristotle realised that if there was to be equality
and Justice then
everything that is exchanged must be somehow comparable. This is the role that is fulfilled by currency [nomisma], so that it becomes, in a way, an intermediate [5, 1133a19–20]
These
lines are significant for two reasons. Firstly the word nomisma
for currency/money is
related to the concepts of custom and law, not to ‘labour and
expenses’. Secondly, ‘intermediate’ is in the sense of a
mediator between two objects, rather than simply as a token, which is
a more modern interpretation. Furthermore, Aristotle defined the
quality that money measured by the word chreia,
which was initially translated to opus
(work), but was later
corrected to indigentia
(need) [22,
pp 68–70]. This is important because it demonstrates that Aristotle
and the Scholastics viewed money as a social construction binding
society by allowing an exchange based on need, rather than as a
simple commodity facilitating the exchange of sensible quantities,
such as labour and expenses.
The
significance of the Scholastic analysis to the development of science
was that when Aristotle discussed measurement in the context of
physics he argued that the measure shared the ‘substance’ of the
measured; this meant that wine was incommensurable with cloth, time
incommensurable with space. The Scholastics realised that money was a
very special measure; it applied to all goods in a market, and only
occasionally shared the substance of the goods. This insight enabled
them to revolutionise the concept of measurement, in a way that
contemporary Muslim scholars did not, and allowed Jean Buridan to
identify the concept of inertia. ([4,
p 263-268], [8,
p 67–74], [22,
pp 65–70])
Out of
Aristotle’s discussion of market exchange, Scholastics developed
the concept of the ‘Just Price’, which has been the subject of
considerable modern debate. For example, Raymond de Roover [10],
argues against viewing the Just Price in a Marxist, labour theory of
value, sense but rather as the market price, in a neo-classical,
liberal sense. However, neither of these modern positions corresponds
to how the Scholastics viewed the concept. The interpretation of the
Just Price we shall employ, based on the Scholastic attitudes to
Aristotle’s description of exchange, is the one discussed by Fabio
Monsalve [24,
pp 6–7]. The Just Price represents an “intellectual construct: an
ideal price that guarantees equality in exchange” and that it
represents a mathematical ‘medium’ or a ‘mean’.
Monsalve
points out that Scholastic analysis was conducted in a definite moral
frame of reference, and so the Just Price “could not refer
indiscriminately to whatever price might be obtained in the market”
[24,
p 8, quoting Langholm]. This aspect was discussed in detail by the
Scholastics prompted by a question ‘Whether the seller is bound to
state the defects of the thing sold?’ posed by the important
Dominican Thomas Aquinas [1,
II, ii, qu. 77, art. 3, ad. 4]. Specifically Aquinas addresses a
problem originating in Stoic philosophy relating to the conduct of a
merchant carrying a supply of food to a starving country. The
merchant knows that they are the first of a number of merchants
bringing food, the question is, should he sell the food at the high
‘market’ price or a lower price based on his knowledge.
Kaye
makes the point that Aquinas separates the Just Price, determined by
divine law, from the ‘market price’, established by men, and
explains that if the Just Price equated with the market price then an
“individual’s responsibility in economic activity is effectively
eliminated” [22,
p 98]. Despite realising this distinction, the answer from Aquinas is
a little surprising. Aquinas observes that the merchant may believe
that there are more
grain shipments on the way, but does not know:
the future is uncertain. On the basis that there is no certainty, and
on the authority of Peter the Chanter, the merchant may charge the
going market price, making an excessive but nevertheless legitimate
profit, though it would be more virtuous to charge the lower price.
Aquinas’
argument was criticised by Pierre Jean Olivi, a leader of the
‘Spiritual Franciscans’. The Spiritual Franciscans argued that
the vow of poverty meant monks should limit their use of property,
usus pauper,
not simply not own property. As a consequence of this extreme
position Olivi was posthumously condemned as a heretic in 1326,
hindering the subsequent transmission of his thought. The
Franciscans, unlike the empirical rationalist Dominicans such as
Thomas Aquinas, were fideists and this philosophical approach meant
that Olivi argued that the metaphysical probability of more grain
arriving had a certain reality, which Aquinas was ignoring [22,
p 121]. Olivi said
The judgement of the value of a thing in exchange seldom or never can be made except through conjecture or probable opinion, and not so precisely, or as if understood and measured by one invisible point, but rather as a fitting latitude within which the diverse judgements of men will differ in estimation [22, p 124].
This
distinction is essential in demarcating the Just Price, an imprecise
abstraction, from the market price, which is observed at a fixed
point [24,
Section 3.2.1].
Olivi
seems to have interacted with merchants and been a close observer of
markets and considered a number of aspects of commerce including the
problem of usury [13,
p 265]. Based on the principle that a lender could charge a borrower
compensation for a loss (interesse)
Olivi recognised that borrowers should compensate lenders for the
‘probable profit’ they could earn by employing capital elsewhere.
Fair exchange was a question of restoring ‘probable equivalence’,
not of precise equality ([22,
p 119], [13,
pp 265–267]). As part of this argument Olivi commented that a
valuation did not only depend on ‘need’ but also on a good’s
scarcity, usefulness and desirability. Since both need and
desirability are subjective, different people will value the same
good differently and based on these ideas, Olivi was able also to
explain the ‘value paradox’ ([30,
pp 60–61], [22,
pp 123–124]). Ultimately, according to James Franklin, Olivi
thought of probability as a trade-able entity, and so could be
quantified [13,
pp 266–267].
The Science of Conjecture
The
Science of Conjecture, or Probability, is the rational method for
dealing with uncertainty. Aristotle classified events into three
types: certain events determined by specific causes; probable events
that usually happened; and unpredictable events, including games of
chance, not amenable to science [17,
p 30]. The development of Probability over the past five hundred
years has been concerned principally with reducing the scope of those
events ‘not amenable to science’.
While
Olivi and merchants developed the idea of probability in relation to
commercial exchange and jurists and theologians addressed questions
of proof the concept of quantifying chance did not fully materialise
until the mid-sixteenth century with Cardano’s Liber
de Ludo Alea. Ian
Hacking has remarked that the emergence of the concept of absolute
chance was late; however, this identification of mathematical
probability in the context of finance precedes both Descartes’
introduction of absolute space (Cartesian co-ordinates) and Newton’s
of absolute time.
Up
until the 1950s, and a re-assessment of his work by Øystein Ore
[27],
Cardano’s contribution to probability theory had been widely
ignored. In the context frequentist interpretations of probability,
that dominated the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, it was
seen as incoherent. More recently, David Bellhouse [2]
has re-evaluated the Liber
looking at it as a
humanist philosophical text, not as a mathematical document, based on
the fact that Cardano, himself, did not list it as one of his
mathematical works. Bellhouse’s hypothesis is that in the Liber
Cardano is trying to
establish under what grounds gambling can be considered ethical in
the context of Nicomachean
Ethics.
Cardano
latches on to the idea that Justice is equivalent to equality and
argues that in dice games ‘equality’ was established by counting
the ways a player could win and comparing that number to the ways a
player would lose. On this basis the ‘chance’ of winning could be
deduced, and if the stakes did not match the chances, the gamble was
unjust. Summarising his findings he states, “a just gamble is one
between willing and knowledgeable players”, making an explicit
association between science and ethics. Almost immediately after
coming to these ethical conclusions, Cardano observes that
These facts contribute a great deal to understanding but hardly anything to practical play [9, p 58 quoting from Chapter 9 of the Liber]
since
they offer nothing to help forecast the outcome of the dice throw.
Throughout
the sixteenth century there was a flow of mathematical thinking from
the vernacular abaco schools into academic circles, not just in the
universities that had declined in status during the Renaissance but
also into the courts of autocrats. For example, Lucca Pacioli was
trained in the abaco tradition, probably by Piero della Francesca,
before working for a Venetian merchant. He then took Franciscan
orders and entered the University of Perugia before ultimately
joining the court of the Milanese autocrat, Lodovico Sforza, where he
taught perspective to Leonardo da Vinci. Thomas Gresham was born into
an important English commercial family around the time Pacioli died
and spent much of his life manipulating the exchange rate in Antwerp
on behalf of the English monarchy. When he died he created the first
chair in mathematics in England with the establishment of Gresham
College, which was the foundation of the Royal Society ([20],
[6]).
Simon Stevin also trained in the abaco tradition and worked as a
merchant’s clerk then as a tax official before moving to the
University of Leiden in 1583. Ten years later he became involved with
the government of the Dutch Republic during the wars of independence
against Spain. As part of the war effort, the Dutch Mathematical
School was established to train military engineers with Stevin as
Director. Stevin’s vocational syllabus attracted soldiers (such as
Descartes) and merchants from across northern Europe and the fees
they paid raised the status of its mathematicians, who when
associated with the scholastic syllabus of abstract arithmetic and
geometry, astronomy and music, were widely regarded as irrelevant.
Stevin wrote a number of textbooks in French or Dutch, not in the
exclusive Latin of the universities, which became read widely and
emphasised the practical
usefulness of
mathematics in everyday life. His influence was profound and forced
other institutions change their curricula; our use of decimal
notation is due to Stevin who recognised its utility in commerce.
([31],
[23,
p 121], [28,
pp 131–132], [11,
p 104])
One
problem Cardano considered was the so-called Problem
of Points which
appears in a text by Pacioli and is based on the following situation:
Two players, F and P, are playing a game based on a sequence of rounds, and each round consists of, for example, the tossing of a fair coin. The winner of the game is the player who is the first to win 7 rounds, and they will win 80 francs.
The
Problem of Points is
how the 80 francs should be split if the game is forced to end after
P has
won 5 rounds while F
has won 4.
Edith
Dudley Sylla notes that the Problem
comes from the abaco
tradition of using ‘stories’ to give examples of how to solve
problems in commercial arithmetic. In this case the Problem
of Points, the story
represents the case of how the capital tied up in a business
partnership should be divided if the venture has to finish
prematurely [33].
Pacioli’s
solution was statistical, the pot should be split 5:4. Cardano
realised this was absurd since it would give a manifestly unfair
result if the game ended after one round out of a hundred or when F
had 99 wins to P’s
90. Cardano makes the point that the correct solution would be
arrived at by considering what would happen in the future, it had to
be forward-looking, in particular it had to account for what ‘paths’
the game would follow. Despite this insight, Cardano’s solution was
still wrong, and the correct solution was provided by Pascal and
Fermat in their correspondence of 1654.
The
Pascal-Fermat solution to the Problem
of Points is widely
regarded as the starting point of mathematical probability. The pair
(it is not known exactly who) realised that when Cardano calculated
that P could
win the pot if the game followed the path PP
(i.e. P
wins and P
wins again) this
actually represented four paths, PPPP,
PPPF,
PPFP,
PPFF,
for the game. It was the players’ ‘choice’ that the game ended
after PP,
not a feature of the game itself and this represents an early example
of mathematicians disentangling behaviour from problem structure.
Calculating the proportion of winning paths would come down to using
the Arithmetic, or Pascal’s, Triangle – the Binomial
distribution. Essentially, Pascal and Fermat established what would
today be recognised as the Cox-Ross-Rubenstein formula [7]
for pricing a digital call option.
The
Pascal–Fermat correspondence was private, the first textbook on
probability was written by Christiaan Huygens in 1656. Huygens had
visited Paris in late 1655 and had been told of the Problem
of Points, but not of
its solution ([9,
p 111], [17,
p 67]), and on his return to the Netherlands he solved the problem
for himself and produced the first treatise on mathematical
probability, Van
Rekeningh in Speelen van Geluck (‘On
the Reckoning of Games of Chance’) in 1657.
In Van
Rekeningh Huygens
starts with, what is essentially, an axiom,
I take as fundamental for such [fair] games that the chance to gain something is worth so much that, if one had it, one could get the same in a fair game, that is a game in which nobody stands to lose. [17, p 69]
Probability
is defined by equating future gain with present value in the context
of ‘fair’ games.
In the
1670’s probability theory developed in the context of Louis XIV’s
appartements du roi,
thrice weekly gambling events that have been described as a ‘symbolic
activity’ not unlike potlach
ceremonies that bind primitive communities [21,
pp 31-42]. This mathematical analysis of an important social activity
stimulated the publication of books describing objective, or
frequentist, probability. The Empirical frequentist approach began to
dominate the mathematical treatment of probability following the
claimed ‘defeat’, or ‘taming’, of chance by mathematics with
the publication of Montmort’s Essay
d’Analyse sur les Jeux de Hazard (‘Analytical
Essay on Games of Chance’) of 1708 and De Moivre’s De
Mensura Sortis (‘The
Measurement of Chance’), of 1711 developed in The
Doctrine of Chances of
1718 [3].
These texts were developed more in the context of gaming rather than
in the analysis of commercial contracts and The
Doctrine was the more
influential, introducing the Central Limit Theorem, and by 1735 it
was believed that there was no longer a class of events that were
‘unpredictable’ [3].
Around
1684 James Bernoulli had begun working on problems in probability and
between 1700 and his death in 1705 he worked on Ars
Conjectandi (‘The
Art of Conjecturing’), a title that emphases the practical rather
than theoretical nature of conjecture, which was published
posthumously in 1713. The Ars
is made up of four
parts, a commentary on Huygens’ Van
Rekeningh, original
work on calculating permutations and combinations, applications of
these ideas to games of chance and finally the application of the
ideas to “civil, moral and economic affairs” [17,
p 224].
While
the first three sections of the Ars
are un-controversial,
the final section is both the most significant and has proved
problematic. Bernoulli, having discussed objective probability at
length introduces the epistemic, or subjective, definition of
probability as “a degree of certainty”. Anders Hald notes that
this is “revolutionary” because Bernoulli is applying mathematics
to propositions, not just to events [17,
p 225]. This section of the Ars
is significant in
that it introduces what would become known as the ‘Law of Large
Numbers’, which can be summarised as collecting a large amount of
data will improve the accuracy of an observation – providing the
system was stationary [17,
p 225]. The section is problematic because Bernoulli considered
situations where the sum of probabilities could be greater than one
[34,
p 27]. This is impossible if probability is calculated as relative
frequency.
Sylla
compared Bernoulli’s work to that of Huygens’ and other
contemporaries, de Witt and de Moivre, in the process of translating
the Ars and
concluded that
equity among associates or partners rather than probabilities in the sense of relative frequencies provided the foundation for the earliest mathematical probability theory. [34, p 13]
and
that
While traditional histories of mathematical probability start with Pierre Fermat, Pascal and Huygens because they give what are from the modern point of view correct frequentist solutions to the problems of division and expectations in games of chance …the foundations of Huygens’ method (…) was not chance (frequentist probability), but rather sors (expectation) in so far as it was involved in implicit contracts and the just treatment of partners. [34, p 28]
In
the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries the motivation for the
development of probability was in the ethical analysis of commercial
contracts where Justice, or balanced reciprocity, ‘fairness’
dominated. The later Empirical approach to probability, based on
observing relative frequencies, emerged out of the simpler analysis
of games of chance in the context of fixed odds.
The
case that Huygens was working in the context of Virtue Ethics is
enhanced by recognising the difficulty he had in translating Van
Rekeningh into Latin
[15,
pp 93–94]. Huygens struggled to translate the Dutch word kans
(‘chance’,
‘lot’), which would normally be translated as sors,
and eventually he, or his editor van Schooten, chose expectatio,
giving the English term ‘expectation’ (in the mathematical
sense). However, Huygens had considered using the Latin word spes
[15,
p 95] which was the term for the virtue ‘Hope’. In French,
espérance is
used when referring to mathematical expectation, reflecting this
debate. The Dutch, who following Stevin’s focus on teaching
mathematics in the vernacular, use their own terms in mathematics, in
this case the equivalent is verwachting:
hope, promise, expectation, forecast, prognosis.
Sylla
also observes that The
Port Royal Logic, a
significant influence on Pascal, notes that “because the house
takes part of the stakes, lotteries are manifestly unfair” and
seventeenth century mathematicians recognised a distinction between
actual gambles, involving transaction costs, and idealised,
frictionless, markets, suitable for the mathematical study by
academics. [33,
p 327]
References
[1]
Thomas Aquinas. Summa
Theologica. Benziger
Bros, 1947.
[3]
D. Bellhouse. Banishing fortuna:
Montmort and De Moivre. Journal
of the History of
Ideas, 69(4):pp.
559–581, 2008.
[5]
S. Broadie and C. Rowe. Aristotle:
Nicomachean Ethics: Translation, Introduction,
Commentary.
Oxford University Press, 2011.
[6]
J. W. Burgon. The
Life and Times of Sir Thomas Gresham: Volume 2.
Adamant Media Corporation, 2004.
[7]
J. C. Cox, S. A. Ross, and M. Rubinstein. Option pricing: A
simplified approach. Journal
of Financial Economics,
7:229–263, 1979.
[9]
F. N. David. Games,
Gods and Gambling, A history of Probability and Statistical
Ideas.
Charles Griffin & Co (Dover), 1962 (1998).
[10]
R. de Roover. The concept of the Just Price: Theory and economic
policy. The
Journal of Economic
History,
18(4):418–434, 1958.
[13]
J. Franklin. The
Science of Conjecture: Evidence and Probability before Pascal.
Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001.
[16]
R. W. Hadden. On
the Shoulders of Merchants: Exchange and the Mathematical
Conception of Nature
in Early Modern Europe.
State University of New York Press, 1994.
[17]
A. Hald. A History
of Probability and Statisctics and their Applications before 1750.
Wiley, 1990.
[18]
A. Heeffer. The Abbaco Tradition (1300-1500): Its role in the
development of European algebra. Published in Suuri Kaiseki Kenkyuujo
koukyuuroku (Japan), 2008.
[19]
S. Homer and R. Sylla. A
History of Interest Rates.
Rutgers University Press, 3rd edition, 1996.
[20]
F. R. Johnson. Gresham College: Precursor of the Royal Society.
Journal of the
History of Ideas,
1(4):413–438, 1940.
[21]
T. M. Kavanagh. Enlightenment
and the Shadows of Chance: The Novel and the
Culture of Gambling in
Eighteenth–Century France.
Johns Hopkins Univeresity Press, 1993.
[23]
P. Mirowski. More
Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics as Nature’s
Economics.
Cambridge University Press, 1989.
[24]
F. Monsalve. Scholastic just price versus current market price: is
it merely a matter of labelling? The
European Journal of the History of Economic Thought,
In press.
http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/pdf/10.1080/09672567.2012.683019.
[25]
D. Nicholas. Economy. In D. Power, editor, The
Central Middle Ages,
pages 57–90. Oxford University Press, 2006.
[33]
E. D. Sylla. Business ethics, commercial mathematics, and the
origins of mathematical probability. History
of Political Economy,
35:309–337, 2003.
[34]
E. D. Sylla. Commercial arithmetic, theology and the intellectual
foundations of Jacob Bernoulli’s Art
of Conjecturing. In
G. Poitras, editor, Pioneers
of Financial
Economics:
contributions prior to Irving Fisher,
pages 11–45. Edward Elgar, 2006.
Good stuff, Tim. I'm looking forward to reading your paper. Can't do the maths, but the pragmatism, William James and all that, is right up my street.
ReplyDeleteThis might be off topic.... but..... :) ...When I play poker I like to think about it in terms of paths. I'm not sure its the same sense as you mention here, but I find that this way of thinking helps me to balance strategy with tactics. So instead of responding 'blindly' to my estimation of the odds of any particular hand I can better think about the hand in the context of the game (the analogy being that individual actions produce better overall results when guided by the appropriate 'meta-philosophy'). Anyway, I was wondering, with the proliferation of on-line poker - Pokerstars alone has over 100 billion hands recorded - if you think, as I do, that as a data source it might offer some proximal insight into financial markets?
I am currently putting a much stronger Pragmatic stance in the Discussion of the paper, when you read that you might understand why my knee-jerk response to your question is "No".
ReplyDeleteBasically my conception of markets is that they embody 'communicative action' that relies on sincerity, Poker is all about insincerity (bluffing). There, philosophically, I do not think 'gambling' can inform 'speculation'.