Reciprocity is a norm, a rule embedded in financial mathematics,
which permits high rates of interest to poorer, higher risk,
borrowers. This means that phenomena such as debt-bondage can become
prevalent (von Lilienfeld-Toal and Mookherjee, 2010). Voluntary
slavery is a limiting expression of debt-bondage (Genicot, 2002)
and by considering the case of voluntary slavery we can highlight
limitations of, not just, basing lending decisions solely on the norm
of reciprocity, but also, of weaknesses of the utilitarian argument
upon which much neo-classical economic theory is founded.
Contemporary deontological ethics, rooted in Kant, argues that one
should “Act in such a way that you always treat human beings as
persons rather than as things” (Ellerman, 1988:1110) and on
this basis slavery can never be justified and hence voluntary slavery
cannot be permitted. There is a problem for consequentialist ethics
originating in Mill’s foundational statement in On Liberty
the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant. (Mill, 2015:I.9)
Some modern libertarians believe a free individual is free to sell
themselves into slavery (Nozick, 1974:331). Mill, himself, did
not, arguing in On Liberty that
by selling himself for a slave, he abdicates his liberty; he foregoes any future use of it beyond that single act. He therefore defeats, in his own case, the very purpose which is the justification of allowing him to dispose of himself.(Mill, 2015:V.11)
This presents a Russell-like paradox; you are free to do anything
apart from forgo your freedom. This is the approach taken by Austrian
economists who have a deontological injunction on alienating an
individual from their will.
Fuchs (2001) recognises the inadequacy of this argument within a
utilitarian framework. He notes that for Mill a person is only
competent to judge what is in their best interest if (1) they have
had knowledge of the alternatives in question; (2) the ability to
enjoy the options; and (3) they must be able to foresee the probable
consequences of their actions (Fuchs, 2001:236). On this basis,
along with other consequentionalists (see Schwan (2013:759‒761)
for a summary), Fuchs sees the central issue as the permanence of
voluntary slavery. This argument points to one of the fundamental
weaknesses with consequentialist ethics: the individual’s inability
to foresee that far into the future and explains the absolute
rejection of voluntary slavery by Austrian economics.
Schwan (2013) argues that the ‘permanence’ issue could not
have explained Mill’s objection to voluntary slavery because Mill
was also opposed to ‘coolie’ ‒ bonded ‒ labour, which is not
permanent. Schwan (2013:764‒765) resorts to Mill’s paradox
when he argues that “we know a priori that entering
such a contract severs the connection between the individual’s
actions and their conception of the good.”; ultimately society
knows best.
Fuchs (2001:244‒247) offers a more interesting argument when
he distinguishes two types of autonomy underpinning liberty:
‘autonomy1’
and ‘autonomy2’.
‘Autonomy1’
is associated with “authentic representations of and are coherent
with the agent’s own settled ideals” and Fuchs identifies seven
factors “inimical to autonomy1”
including reversibility and a lack of ignorance, indoctrination,
coercion, compulsion and duress. ‘Autonomy2’
is “more limited” and relates to specific actions: “ one can do
what one wants to do and can refrain from doing what one does not
want to do.” Autonomy1
would permit ‘Mormon marriage’ or entry into a convent where an
individuals rights and freedoms are curtailed.
There are two comments on Fuchs’ argument. Firstly, it seems as
much Kantian as consequentialist (White, 2011:11‒13).
Secondly, Fuchs highlights the elitist nature of Mill’s philosophy.
The autonomous agent must be educated (1), be able to appreciate (2)
‒ a very normative concept, Fuchs (2001:236) compares
appreciating a nursery rhyme to Beethoven, coca-cola to Château
Margaux ‒ their choices and an ability to foresee (3).
Archard (1990:464) points out that Mill approves of paternalism
so long as it enhances the individual’s rationality ‒ education
is compulsory ‒ and so their ability to be free. Arguing that
rationality is based on education implies it is cultural and one
could conclude that Fuchs’ ‘autonomy1’
would prohibit an Aztec willingly going to sacrifice because despite
the act being “coherent with the agent’s own settled ideals” we
could argue that the Aztec has been ‘indoctrinated’.
The relevance of the second comment is that for the utilitarian
argument to hold the agent must be securely embedded in society.
Hirschman (1997) identifies that Smith’s ‘hidden hand’,
and hence the utilitarian argument, must have a stake in society and
international relations are based on “a group of states, conscious
of certain common interests and common values, form a society in the
sense that they conceive themselves to be bound by a common set of
rules in their relations with one another” (Bull, 1977:13).
The libertarian admits voluntary slavery, and by implication
debt-bondage, on the basis that the individual is atomised and can
alienate themselves from society. On the other hand, we argue that
the consequentialist, acting as a Kantian, rejects voluntary slavery
because the individual is embedded in society. This realisation is
driving the “re-introduction of ethics into economics” (van
Staveren, 2008; White and van Staveren, 2013). The
practical implication of these standpoints is the libertarian can
accommodate inequality ‒ because this facilitates the separation of
communities into those capable of rationally rejecting voluntary
slavery and those incapable ‒ where as the ethical economist
cannot.
References
Archard, D. (1990). Freedom not to be free: The
case of the slavery contract in J. S. Mill’s On Liberty. The
Philosophical Quarterly (1950-), 40(161):453—465.
Bull, H. (1977). The Anarchical Society: A Study
of Order in World Politics. Columbia University Press.
Ellerman, D. P. (1988). The Kantian
Person/Thing principle in political economy. Journal of
Economic Issues, 22(4):1109—1122.
Fuchs, A. E. (2001). Autonomy, slavery, and
mill’s critique of paternalism. Ethical Theory and Moral
Practice, 4(3):231—251.
Genicot, G. (2002). Bonded labor and serfdom: a
paradox of voluntary choice. Journal of Development
Economics, 67(1):101—127.
Hirschman, A. (1997). The Passions and the
Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism before Its
Triumph. Princeton University Press.
Mill, J. (2015). On liberty. In Philp, M. and
Rosen, F., editors, On Liberty, Utilitarianism and Other
Essays. Oxford University Press.
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia.
Basic Books.
Schwan, D. (2013). J. S. Mill on coolie labour and
voluntary slavery. British Journal for the History of
Philosophy, 21(4):754—766.
van Staveren, I. (2008). Introduction to the
special issue on ethics and economics. Review of Political
Economy, 20(2):159—161.
von Lilienfeld-Toal, U. and Mookherjee, D. (2010).
The political economy of debt bondage. American Economic Journal:
Microeconomics, 2(3):44—84.
White, M. (2011). Kantian Ethics and Economics:
Autonomy, Dignity, and Character. Stanford University Press.
White, M. and van Staveren, I. (2013). Ethics
and Economics: New Perspectives. Taylor & Francis.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.