I was invited by the “London Markets Actuarial Group”, made
up of general insurance actuaries, to speak at an ethics workshop. This post is
about some observations I have from this experience. My observations are
critical. This does not mean I believe actuaries are not well-intentioned,
rather there might be gaps in their understanding that inhibit clear ethical
reasoning. The purpose is to highlight how ethical assumptions are always
questionable and it is by asking questions that an individual becomes ethical.
The context is that the professional body of UK actuaries, the
IFoA, requires members to undertake two hours CPD on ethics a year and the
workshop was a means to accomplish this requirement. I had been asked to
comment on, amongst other topics: whether ethics just comes down to personal
opinion; what is meant by “the public interest” and some comment on how ethics
relates to managing risks, the core competence of actuaries. The organizer came
up with some simple “cases” to make my theoretical session more interactive.
I began by asserting that ethics was not personal with the
explanation that ethical norms were socially constructed and rooted in culture.
This basis does not imply that ethical norms are necessarily relative. I gave
the examples of truth telling and promise keeping as being essential to enable
communication (without mentioning higher order moral absolutism and token
absolutism). I explained that “emotivism”, the attitude that moral statements
are simply expressions of personal preferences developed in the context of
twentieth century logical-positivism and is, today, rather peripheral. I observed
that emotivism, as a branch of non-cognitivism, is based in Hume’s idea that
moral judgements are essentially passions (desires that motivate action). I
suggest that this is an error, in that the motivating desire is a well-running
society and moral norms are thus a means to fulfil that desire. The norm of
truth telling is not the aim; effective communication is, truth telling is a
rational means of achieving communication.
I also made the observation that “being ethical” was not the
same as being a “good person”. The point here is that ethics requires thought
and reason. Kant made the point, which is contested, that an impulsive act
might be good but cannot be ethical. The importance of distinguishing being
“good” from being “ethical” is that if questions are approached on the basis of
“good” and “bad” the discussion can quickly become polarised, inhibiting
discussion, which actually inhibits ethical consideration. A common experience
is when politics comes down to being “good” rather than seeking an effective
means of attaining policy ends (which are typically common across the political
spectrum).
I then, very briefly, summarise the three main approaches to
ethics: consequentialist, deontological and character. I began with
consequentialism because it is so dominant in finance, mentioning that there
are fundamental issues with the foundations of consequentialism; such as, how
are consequences identified and assessed and how are they weighted for
different people. I gave the classical example of someone taking a lonely
neighbour out for a coffee; if the neighbour was killed by a car on the way
home, as a consequence of the act, consequentialism would be critical of the
actions, though most would think the act of kindness was morally right. I then
moved on to a similarly brief explanation of deontological ethics, emphasising
their basis in promulgated rules before discussing Kant’s categorical
imperative, though I don’t think I mentioned the requirement to treat others as
ends in themselves, and not means to an end.
There followed a discussion of the following “case”
- Your firm uses a sophisticated renewal pricing algorithm, so that the least price-sensitive customers will be charged a higher price.
- You are aware of the regulatory concerns about this practice, and so the algorithm has been adjusted to cap the prices for those customers that could be categorised as “vulnerable”.
- This approach means that your firm offers insurance to a far wider customer base than would otherwise be the case.
I noted that the second point seems to address deontological
concerns while the third appears to justify the practice on consequentialist
terms. I then mentioned that I had recently seen my car insurance quote, from
the same provider, drop 30% by asking for quotes from a price comparison
website. I observed that, as a customer, I had issues with this type of
practice.
An initial comment was that customers who shop around were
lower risk, and so should pay lower premiums. My observation here is that
ethical reasoning must be based on matters of fact. For example, I cannot
justify sacrificing children because the sacrificial act appeases the great god
and will improve crop yields; this justification is not factual. In the case
presented, I would challenge whether there was a causal relationship between
“shopping around” and being a lower risk driver. There may be a correlation,
but actuaries should be competent at understanding correlation is not
causation. The correlation between “shopping around” and “low risk” is likely a
consequence of a common underlying factor, such as education. This is covered
by quoting based on occupation meaning that the explanation that “shopping
around” is relevant information is a bit dubious.
The fundamental ethical issue here is to what extent are
insurers treating their customers as ends in themselves, rather than as a means
to a personal (corporate) end? The response would probably be that customers
are free to shop around and since the insurers are not inhibiting the customers
autonomy there is no problem. I think this is open to discussion.
I was left wondering how familiar actuaries are with
emergent issues around algorithmic decision-making being highly discriminatory.
Two, of many, books on the topic are: The Black Box
Society: The Secret Algorithms That Control Money and Information written
by a lawyer (the HUP page has lots of additional resources); Weapons of Math Destruction:
How Big Data Increases Inequality and Threatens Democracy written by a
mathematician. Actuaries are free to disagree with these accounts, but they
should be aware that these debates are important and might impact actuarial
practice in the future.
Another comment made by a participant, I can’t recall if it
was at this point, was that insurers need to be flexible in pricing to allow
cross-subsidisation. I think the context was that margins on car insurance were
very tight and so profits had to be sought elsewhere. Well established
financial theory (for example, Risk
Uncertainty and Profit) would suggest that the margins on car insurance, a
mature business with lots of relevant data, should be almost non-existent; the
market is working well if the margins are tight. What is less clear is why there
should be cross-subsidies in car insurance?
Cross subsidising, the practice of charging higher prices to
one type of consumers to artificially lower prices for another group, is not the
same as pooling, as pooling is amongst similar consumers and a core competency
of actuaries is to discriminate different types of customers. Since there are legal
and regulatory
issues around cross-subsidies, I was surprised to hear this being offered as a justification
for specific pricing policies, since they may create operational (regulatory or
legal) risks. One moral issue is: what gives insurers the right to determine
which type of consumer should be being subsidised and which type should be
being penalised?
I think another justification offered (it might have come up
elsewhere) was that as long as a contract was transparent there were no ethical
issues with offering that contract: the customer is free to accept or decline a
clearly presented contract. I am not sure of the ethical basis of this
approach, it seems to be rooted in “ethical egoism”, the view
that someone acting in their own self-interest is acting morally. This ethical
approach is associated with libertarian politics. If this is the ethical basis
then it would be incoherent with the apparent fact that insurers are being
paternalistic in determining who subsidises who. A general criticism of ethical
egoism is that people often do not know what is actually in their
“self-interest” for various reasons: is it long-term or short-term
self-interest; do individuals have the cognitive/psychological capability to
establish their self-interest; is their tacit coercion involved.
Whether or not the “transparency” argument can be justified
ethically, that is rationally, is a moot point since there is legal principle
in English law that a person must have “capacity” to
enter a contract. In US law, “capacity” is assumed if the contractor is old
enough, it is not so clear in English law. This issue played a part in the PPI
mis-selling scandal and is reflected in the change to the Actuaries’ Code 6.4
Where Members identify that a user of their work has, or is reasonably likely to have, misunderstood or misinterpreted the information or advice provided by them in a way which could have a material impact, Members should draw the user’s attention to this.
There is a lot of judgement involved in “has, or is
reasonably likely to have, misunderstood or misinterpreted the information”.
The requirement is not simply that the terms are clear and transparent in the
eyes of a well-educated actuary, the “reasonably likely” clause is open to
interpretation and a court is likely to regard what is “clear” to a
well-educated actuary might not be clear to their client.
Returning to the case under discussion, I observed that
while it might appear to conform to some consequentialist or deontological
ethical frameworks it did appear to be “unfair”. The concept of “fairness” is
closely related to the third major ethical framework: character or virtue
ethics.
Aristotle is usually recognised as the key proponent of
virtue ethics. I explained his approach was based on the idea that everything
has an “ends” or purpose. This apples to inanimate physical objects, the
purpose of a chair is to support a sitting person; different chairs have
different specific purposes (dining, arm, desk, …). “Virtues” lead to the
successful attainment of the purpose. Aristotle argued that the purpose of
humans was eudaimonia, often
translated as “happiness” though I think “equilibrium” is better. The Greeks
identified the four cardinal virtues: prudence (wisdom), courage (fortitude)
and temperance (decorum) and to clarify I pointed out that the three central
characters of the Harry Potter novels represented these three core virtues.
The fourth Greek virtue is justice. In this context, justice
is seen as the virtue (quality) of a functionally differentiated system that
enables the system to work well (to achieve its purpose). For example, a
functioning computer system can be seen as possessing the virtue of justice.
Justice is the virtue of a community that enables different people to work well
together to deliver a well-functioning society. Just as truth-telling and
promise-keeping are essential to justice, the well running of a society,
reciprocity, or fairness, is essential to all but the most primitive societies.
The significance of reciprocity only emerges in
societies based on commercial exchange, reinforcing the idea that ethical
norms are socially constructed in order to support the coherence of that
society. A significant proportion of my research is concerned with
understanding how the
ethical norm of reciprocity is embedded in financial economics.
Having reviewed the different ethical frameworks I spoke a
bit about “public interests”. I feel this was rather weak/irrelevant in the
context. My aim was to introduce the idea that Adam Smith “created” capitalism
by suggesting that “passions” (private interests) and “interests” (public interests)
could be balance in monetary terms. This is the ethical justification of the
modern financial imperative to maximise expected utility (of money).
Following this presentation the following case was
introduced
- You are asked to price a new product
- This will be provided on a wholesale, net priced basis to your distribution partner
- Although the product is expected to generate very few claims, the consumer perception of risk is much greater than this
- Your distribution partner is therefore expecting to sell the product for a very high mark up.
- They are also happy for you to set a relatively conservative initial net price for the product, as long as there is a 100% profit commission to the distributor once you have made your agreed margi
A comment about this case was along the lines that all
companies “mark up” and the example of the mark-up
on men’s razors was offered. I thought about this comment for a while, the
reason I did this was considering whether a full response would be possible in
the time available. I decided it would not have been but I can outline the
issues here.
Firstly, I believe there is a false equivalence, in general,
between selling razors and providing insurance. My evidence for this is in the
fact that actuaries are licensed professionals, where as razor manufacturers
are not. There are two aspects to this. Licensing, or regulating, professions means
that those engaged in the profession must demonstrate technical skills and meet
standards of behaviour. In compensation, licensing limits competition and so
they can charge premium rates. Economic libertarians (see before) are
fundamentally opposed to licensing on the basis that there should be a free
market in goods and services. To assert that there is an equivalence between
being an actuary and razor manufacturer/retailer misses this point and the fact
that actuaries’ fees are already inflated: charging high mark-ups could be seen
rent seeking.
Secondly, as can be deduced by my appearance, razors are not
a necessity where as I am required to take out insurance if I wish to drive or
borrow money. This would suggest that mark-ups in insurance contravene Kant’s
injunction to treat people as ends not means. Therefore, I do not think it is tenable
to justify high mark-ups in insurance on the basis of high mark-ups on the
basis of razors.
Passing over the specifics of the comment there is the issue
as to whether it is legitimate to “take more than what is given”, for a
commercial transaction not to conform to the norm of reciprocity or “fairness
in exchange”. The ethical justification for charging high mark-ups is the main
moral imperative of economics: to maximise profit. This is rooted in a
synthesis of Mill’s utilitarianism: right action is the action that produces
the greatest good to the greatest number, synthesised with Smith’s claim that wealth
can measure “passions” and “interests”. There are significant philosophical issues
with both these supporting principles and this economic imperative is losing
its influence, though I recognise I am in a minority of those
sympathetic to finance in rejecting this imperative (in favour of the norm of
reciprocity).
From the early 1950s the profit maximisation principle was
established in English case law in Buttle v Saunders,
where it was ruled that profit maximisation superseded any concept of “commercial
morality”. This case was later employed to prevent the National Union of Miners
investing the miners pension fund in support of miners “political”, rather than
financial, interests (Cowan v Scargill). This century, concerns over the
ability of investment funds to invest “ethically”, and divest in hydrocarbons,
for example, led to a re-think and there is widespread
doubt today that “profit maximisation” is the economic imperative in finance.
An actuary might well argue that arguing against the ethical legitimacy of mark-ups is utopian and impractical. However, there is good evidence to support the belief that not imposing mark-ups is fundamental to sound finance. The evidence is in the practice of "dual quoting", simultaneously giving bid and ask prices without knowing which position the counterparty will take. This was the basis of jobbing the London markets for centuries. Dual quoting imposes sincerity on jobbers; they are unable to set high mark-ups without them being clearly obvious in a wide spread. A razor retailer could not impose a 4000% mark-up if they were required to simultaneously quote a price at which they would buy razors. This might seem rather absurd, but there is evidence that Quaker retailers would "dual quote" as part of their commitment to "honest dealing". It is worth noting that the influence on global finance and English commerce of a small number of Quakers is profound: Barclays, Lloyds, Waterhouse, Friends Provident, Boots, Clarks and the British industrial revolution was built on the Quaker Coalbrookdale Iron Company and Stockton & Darlington Railway. Being honest in pricing seems to promote persistence in business.
Dual quoting has a mathematical relevance. Modern subjectivist approaches to statistics, including Bayesian methods, were initially justified using the example of dual quoting by Frank Ramsey, the "Dutch Book Argument".
An actuary might well argue that arguing against the ethical legitimacy of mark-ups is utopian and impractical. However, there is good evidence to support the belief that not imposing mark-ups is fundamental to sound finance. The evidence is in the practice of "dual quoting", simultaneously giving bid and ask prices without knowing which position the counterparty will take. This was the basis of jobbing the London markets for centuries. Dual quoting imposes sincerity on jobbers; they are unable to set high mark-ups without them being clearly obvious in a wide spread. A razor retailer could not impose a 4000% mark-up if they were required to simultaneously quote a price at which they would buy razors. This might seem rather absurd, but there is evidence that Quaker retailers would "dual quote" as part of their commitment to "honest dealing". It is worth noting that the influence on global finance and English commerce of a small number of Quakers is profound: Barclays, Lloyds, Waterhouse, Friends Provident, Boots, Clarks and the British industrial revolution was built on the Quaker Coalbrookdale Iron Company and Stockton & Darlington Railway. Being honest in pricing seems to promote persistence in business.
Dual quoting has a mathematical relevance. Modern subjectivist approaches to statistics, including Bayesian methods, were initially justified using the example of dual quoting by Frank Ramsey, the "Dutch Book Argument".
The point I went on to make is that ethics is fundamentally
concerned with questioning one’s behaviours. In this sense it is as “scientific” as physics,
which questions phenomena in the physical world rather than the social. Ethical
norms are nothing more, or less, than the norms that ensure a particular
society “works”.
On this basis, I finished my presentation by drawing links
between ethics and risk management. I pointed out that the three pillars of
Basel II corresponded to the three main ethical frameworks (Minimum capital
requirements are deontological rules; Supervisory review relates to the
character of the firm; Market discipline is concerned with consequences). I
also described the failure of LTCM and the success of J.P. Morgan through the
Credit Crisis in terms of ethics.
The failure of LTCM
is widely understood as being a consequence of reckless trading. Donald
MacKenzie has a different explanation that suggests the firm’s failure was more
to do with their social isolation, rooted in their success and consequent envy
of others. Their downfall was precipitated by the poor drafting of a fax and a
lack of support when beliefs about their solvency started to spread. The
success of J.P.
Morgan through the Credit Crisis was based on the fact that they questioned
assumptions of prices their models produced, this self-examination is
fundamentally ethical.
These closing remarks were designed to emphasise the practical
and serious utility of ethical behaviour. Ethics can be viewed as vacuous
philosophical introspection irrelevant to daily life, or mundane cases that address
clear situations. Ethics comes into its own when people work out what
behaviours will prove beneficial in their daily lives.
Plato argued it was impossible to be knowingly un-ethical,
bad behaviour was a consequence of ignorance. Pushing this, and the line taken
by Aristotle and Kant, unethical behaviour is always a consequence of people
not thinking about their behaviour. The problem with ethics, and all social, as
opposed to physical, phenomena, is that the rules of the game are fluid. Most
of the audience in the workshop would have been taught that profit maximisation
was the moral imperative, and on this basis they offered the comments
presented. A problem will develop if society shifts its consensus away from
profit maximisation and towards social cohesion, and so actuaries become
isolated from the society they inhabit. This is a risk management problem and
mirrors the type of situation investment managers face: will the fundamentals change.
It is, and should be, a responsibility of the IFoA to horizon scan these shifts
and reflect them in its approach to professionalism. I perceive changes in the
Actuaries’ Code, such as in regard to Communication, being a response to this
foresight. If actuaries, or finance in general, become disconnected from
society they will find their support network, potentially including their
status as a licensed profession, evaporating, just as LTCM saw their status as “masters
of the universe” disappear. This is why ethics are important.
P.S. One participant commented that the workshop had been Euro-centric. This is true for the following reasons. Time did not allow me to point out links between European and Chinese philosophical approaches. Actuarial science is a product of European thought, if an actuaries employed techniques that had emerged out of Buddhist societies the workshop would have placed greater emphasis on Buddhist ethics. To try and apply Buddhist ethics to Euro-centric actuarial practices is going to be tough.
P.S. One participant commented that the workshop had been Euro-centric. This is true for the following reasons. Time did not allow me to point out links between European and Chinese philosophical approaches. Actuarial science is a product of European thought, if an actuaries employed techniques that had emerged out of Buddhist societies the workshop would have placed greater emphasis on Buddhist ethics. To try and apply Buddhist ethics to Euro-centric actuarial practices is going to be tough.