This is now published, open access.
Within the field of Financial Mathematics, the Fundamental Theorem of Asset Pricing consists of two statements, (e.g. [Shreve, 2004, Section 5.4])
Theorem: The Fundamental Theorem of Asset Pricing
1. A market admits no arbitrage, if and only if, the market has a martingale measure.Within the field of Financial Mathematics, the Fundamental Theorem of Asset Pricing consists of two statements, (e.g. [Shreve, 2004, Section 5.4])
Theorem: The Fundamental Theorem of Asset Pricing
2. The martinagale measure is unique, if and only if, every contingent claim can be hedged.
The use of the term ‘probability measure’ places the Fundamental Theory within the mathematical theory of probability formulated by Andrei Kolmogorov in 1933 ([Kolmogorov, 1933 (1956)]). Kolmogorov’s work took place in a context captured by Bertrand Russell, who in 1927 observed that
It is important to realise the fundamental position of probability in science. …As to what is meant by probability, opinions differ. Russell [1927 (2009), p 301]
Two mathematical theories had become ascendant by the late 1920s. Richard von Mises, an
Austrian engineer linked to the Vienna Circle of logical-positivists, and brother of the economist
Ludwig, attempted to lay down the axioms of probability based on observable facts within a
framework of Platonic-Realism. The result was published in German in 1931 and popularised in
English as Probability, Statistics and Truth and is now regarded as a key justification of the
frequentist approach to probability.
To balance von Mises’ Realism, the Italian actuary, Bruno de Finetti presented a more
Nominalist approach. De Finetti argued that “Probability does not exist” because it was only an
expression of the observer’s view of the world. De Finetti’s subjectivist approach was closely related
to the less well-known position taken by Frank Ramsey, who, in 1926, published Probability and
Truth, in which he argued that probability was a measure of belief. Ramsey’s argument was
well-received by his friend and mentor John Maynard Keynes but his early death hindered its
development.
While von Mises and de Finetti took an empirical path, Kolmogorov used mathematical
reasoning to define probability. Kolmogorov wanted to adress they key issue for physics at the time
which was that was that, following the work of Montmort and de Moivre in the first decode of the
eighteenth century, probability had been associated with counting events and comparing relative
frequencies. This had been coherent until mathematics became focused on infinite sets at the
same time as physics became concerned with statistical mechanics in the second half of
the nineteenth century. Von Mises had tried to address these issues but his analysis was
weak in dealing with infinite sets, that came with continuous time. As Jan von Plato
observes
In 1902 Lebesgue had redefined the mathematical concept of the integral in terms of abstract
‘measures’ in order to accommodate new classes of mathematical functions that had emerged in the
wake of Cantor’s transfinite sets. Kolmogorov made the simple association of these abstract
measures with probabilities, solving the von Mises’ issue of having to deal with infinite
sets in an ad hoc manner. As a result Kolmogorov identified a random variable with a
function and an expectation with an integral, probability became a branch of Analysis, not
Statistics.
Kolmogorov’s work was initially well received, but slow to be adopted. One contemporary
American reviewer noted it was an important proof of Bayes’ Theorem ([Reitz, 1934]), then still
controversial (Keynes [1972, Ch XVI, 13]) but now a cornerstone of statistical decision making.
Amongst English-speaking mathematicians, the American Joseph Doob was instrumental in
promoting probability as measure ([Doob, 1941]) while the full adoption of the approach followed its
advocacy by Doob and William Feller at the First Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics
and Probability in 1945–1946.
While measure theoretic probability is a rigorous theory outside pure mathematics it is seen as
redundant. Von Mises criticised it as un-necessarily complex ([von Mises, 1957 (1982), p 99]) while
the statistician Maurice Kendall argued that measure theory was fine for mathematicians, but of
limited practical use to statisticians and fails “to found a theory of probability as a branch of
scientific method” ([Kendall, 1949, p 102]). More recently the physicist Edwin Jaynes champions
Leonard Savage’s subjectivism as having a “deeper conceptual foundation which allows it to
be extended to a wider class of applications, required by current problems of science”
in comparison with measure theory ([Jaynes, 2003, p 655]). Furthermore in 2001 two
mathematicians Glenn Shafer and Vladimir Vovk, a former student of Kolmogorov, proposed
an alternative to measure-theoretic probability, ‘game-theoretic probability’, because
the novel approach “captures the basic intuitions of probability simply and effectively”
([Shafer and Vovk, 2001]). Seventy-five years on Russell’s enigma appears to be no closer to
resolution.
The issue around the ‘basic intuition’ of measure theoretic probability for empirical
scientists can be accounted for as a lack of physicality. Frequentist probability is based on
the act of counting, subjectivist probability is based on a flow of information, where as
measure theoretic probability is based on an abstract mathematical object unrelated
to phenomena. Specifically in the Fundamental Theorem, the ‘martingale measure’ is a
probability measure, usually labelled ℚ, such that the price of an asset today, X0 is the
expectation, under the martingale measure, of the discounted asset prices in the future,
XT
Given a current asset price X0, and a set of future prices, XT the probability distribution ℚ is
defined such that this equality holds, and so is forward looking, in the fact that it is
based on current and future prices. The only condition placed on the relationship that the
martingale measure has with the ‘natural’, or ‘physical’, probability measure, inferred from
historical price changes and usually assigned the label ℙ, is that they agree on what is
possible.
The term ‘martingale’ in this context derives from doubling strategies in gambling and it was introduced into mathematics by Jean Ville in 1939, in a critique of von Mises work, to label a random process where the value of the random variable at a specific time is the expected value of therandom variable in the future. The concept that asset prices have the martingale property was first proposed by Benoit Mandlebrot ([Mandelbrot, 1966]) in response to an early formulation of Eugene Fama’s Efficient Market Hypothesis (EMH) ([Fama, 1965]), the two concepts being combined by Fama in 1970 ([Fama, 1970]). For Mandelbrot and Fama the key consequence of prices being martingales was that the price today was, statistically, independent of the future price distribution: technical analysis of markets was charlatanism. In developing theEMH there is no discussion on the nature of the probability under which assets are martingales, and it is often assumed that the expectation is calculated under the natural measure.
Arbitrage, the word derives from ‘arbitration’, has long been a subject of financial mathematics.
In Chapter 9 of his 1202 text advising merchants, the Liber Abaci, Fibonacci discusses ‘Barter of
Merchandise and Similar Things’,
In this case there are three commodities, arms of cloth, rolls of cotton and Pisan pounds, and
Fibonacci solves the problem by having Pisan pounds ‘arbitrate’ between the other two
commodities.
Over the centuries this technique of pricing through arbitration evolved into the law of one price,
that if two assets offer identical cash flows then they must have the same price. This was employed
by Jan de Witt in 1671 when he solved the problem of pricing life annuities in terms of redeemable
annuities, based on the presumption that
the real value of certain expectations or chances of objects, of different value, should be estimated by that which we can obtain from as many expectations or chances dependent on one or several equitable contracts. [Sylla, 2003, p 313, quoting De Witt, The Worth of Life Annuities in Proportion to Redeemable Bonds]
In 1908 the Croatian mathematician, Vincent Bronzin, published a text which discusses pricing
derivatives by ‘covering’, or hedging them, them with portfolios of options and forward contracts
employing the principle of ‘equivalence’, the law of one price ([Zimmermann and Hafner, 2007]). In
1965 the functional analyst and probabilist, Edward Thorp, collaborated with a post-doctoral
mathematician, Sheen Kassouf, and combined the law of one price with basic techniques of
calculus to identify market mis-pricing of warrant prices, at the time a widely traded stock
option. In 1967 they published their methodology in a best-selling book, Beat the Market
([MacKenzie, 2003]).
Within economics, the law of one price was developed in a series of papers between 1954 and
1964 by Kenneth Arrow, Gerard Debreu and Lionel MacKenzie in the context of general
equilibrium. In his 1964 paper, Arrow addressed the issue issue of portfolio choice in the presence of
risk and introduced the concept of an Arrow Security, an asset that would pay out ‘1’ in a specific
future state of the economy but zero for all other states, and by the law of one price, all
commodities could be priced in terms of these securities ([Arrow, 1964]). The work of
Fischer Black, Myron Scholes and Robert Merton ([Black and Scholes, 1973]) employed the
principal and presented a mechanism for pricing warrants on the basis that “it should
not be possible to make sure profits” with the famous Black-Scholes equation being the
result.
In the context of the Fundamental Theorem, ‘an arbitrage’ is the ability to formulate a trading
strategy such that the probability, whether under ℙ or ℚ, of a loss is zero, but the probability of a
profit is positive. This definition is important following Hardie’s criticism of the way the term is
applied loosely in economic sociology ([Hardie, 2004]). The obvious point of this definition is that,
unlike Hardie’s definition [Hardie, 2004, p 243], there is no guaranteed (strictly positive) profit,
however there is also a subtle technical point: there is no guarantee that there is no loss if there is an
infinite set of outcomes. This is equivalent to the observation that there is no guarantee that an
infinite number of monkeys with typewriters will, given enough time, come up with a work
of Shakespeare: it is only that we expect them to do so. This observation explains the
caution in the use of infinite sets taken by mathematicians such as Poincare, Lebesgue and
Brouwer.
To understand this meaning of arbitrage, consider the most basic case of a single
period economy, consisting of a single asset whose price, X0, is known at the start of
the period and can take on one of two (present) values, XT U > X
T D, representing two
possible states of the economy at the end of the period. In this case an arbitrage would
exist if XT U > X
T D ≥ X
0, buying the asset now would lead to a possible profit at the
end of the period, with the guarantee of no loss. Similarly, if X0 ≥ XT U > X
T D, short
selling the asset now, and buying it back at the end of the period would also lead to an
arbitrage.
In summary, for there to be no arbitrage opportunities we require that
This
implies that there is a real number, q, 0 ≥ q ≥ 1 such that
X0 = | XT D + q(X T U - X T D) | ||
= | qXT U + (1 - q)X T D | ||
≡ | Eℚ[XT ], |
With this in mind, the first statement of the Fundamental Theorem can be interpreted
simply as “the price of an asset must lie between its maximum and minimum possible
(discounted) future price”. If X0 > XT D we have that q< 0 where as if X
T U<X
0 then
q >1, and in both cases q does not represent a probability measure, which, by definition
must lie between 0 and 1. In this simple case there is a trivial intuition behind measure
theoretic probability, the martingale measure and an absence of arbitrage are a simple
tautology.
To appreciate the meaning of the second statement of the theorem, consider the situation when
the economy can take on three states at the end of the time period, not two. If we label possible
future asset prices as XT U > X
T M >X
T D, we cannot deduce a unique set of probabilities
0 ≤ qU,qM,qD ≤ 1, with qU + qM + qD = 1, such that
Most models employed in practice ignore the impact of transaction costs, on the utopian basis
that precision will improve as market structures evolve and transaction costs disappear. Situations
where there are many, possibly infinitely many, prices at the end of the period are handled by
providing a model for asset price dynamics, between times 0 and T. The choice of asset price
dynamics defines the distribution of XT , either under the martingale or natural probability measure,
and in making the choice of asset price dynamics, the derivative price is chosen. This effect is similar
to the choice of utility function determining the results of models in some areas of welfare
economics.
The Fundamental Theorem is not well known outside the limited field of financial mathematics,
practitioners focus on the models that are a consequence of the Theorem where as social scientists
focus on the original Black-Scholes-Merton model as an exemplar. Practitioners are daily exposed to
the imprecision of the models they useand are skeptical, if not dismissive, of the validity of the
models they use ([Miyazaki, 2007, pp 409-410 ], [MacKenzie, 2008, p 248], [Haugh and
Taleb, 2009]). Following the market crash of 1987, few practioners used the Black-Scholes equation
to actually ‘price’ options, rather they used the equation to measure market volatility, a proxy for
uncertainty.
However, the status of the Black-Scholes model as an exemplar in financial economics has been
enhanced following the adoption of measure theoretic probability, and this can be understood
because the Fundamental Theorem, born out of Black-Scholes-Merton, unifies a number of distinct
theories in financial economics. MacKenzie ([MacKenzie, 2003, p 834]) describes a dissonance
between Merton’s derivation of the model (Merton [1973]) using techniques from stochastic
calculus, and Black’s, based on the Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM) (Black and
Scholes [1973]). When measure theoretic probability was introduced it was observed that the
Radon-Nikodym derivative, a mathematical object that describes the relationship between the
stochastic processes Merton used in the natural measure and the martingale measure,
involved the market-price of risk (Sharpe ratio), a key object in the CAPM. This point
was well understood in the academic literature in the 1990s and was introduced into the
fourth edition of the standard text book, Hull’s Options, Futures and other Derivatives, in
2000.
The realisation that the Fundamental Theorem unified Merton’s approach, based on stochastic
calculus advocated by Samuelson at M.I.T, CAPM, which had been developed at the Harvard
Business School and in California, martingales, a feature of efficient markets that had been proposed
at Chicago and incomplete markets, from Arrow and Debreu in California, enhanced the status of
Black-Scholes-Merton as representing a Kuhnian paradigm. This unification of a plurality of
techniques within a ‘theory of everything’ came just as the Black-Scholes equation came under
attack for not reflecting empirical observations of market prices and obituaries were being written for
the broader neoclassical programme ([Colander, 2000])and can explain why, in 1997, the Nobel Prize
in Economics was awarded to Scholes and Merton “for a new method to determine the value of
derivatives”.
The observation that measure theoretic probability unified a ‘constellation of beliefs, values, techniques’ in financial economics can be explained in terms of the transcendence of mathematics. To paraphrase Tait ([Tait, 1986, p 341])
The observation that measure theoretic probability unified a ‘constellation of beliefs, values, techniques’ in financial economics can be explained in terms of the transcendence of mathematics. To paraphrase Tait ([Tait, 1986, p 341])
A mathematical proposition is about a certain structure, financial markets. It refers to prices and relations among them. If it is true, it is so in virtue of a certain fact about this structure. And this fact may obtain even if we do not or cannot know that it does.
In this sense, the Fundamental Theorem confirms the truth of the EMH, or any other of the other ‘facts’
that go into the proposition. It becomes doctrine that more (derivative) assets need to be created in
order to complete markets, or as Miyazaki observes [Miyazaki, 2007, pp 404 ], speculative activity as
arbitration, is essential for market efficiency.
However, this relies on the belief in the transcendence of mathematics. If mathematics is a human construction, it does not hold true.
However, this relies on the belief in the transcendence of mathematics. If mathematics is a human construction, it does not hold true.
References
K. J. Arrow. The role of securities in the optimal allocation of risk-bearing. The Review
of Economic Studies, 31(2):91–96, 1964.
F. Black and M. Scholes. The pricing of options and corporate liabilities. Journal of
Political Economy, 81(3):637–654, 1973.
D. Colander. The death of neoclassical economics. Journal of the History of Economic
Thought, 22(2):127, 2000.
E. F. Fama. Efficient capital markets: A review of theory and empirical work. The Journal
of Finance, 25(2):383–417, 1970.
I. Hardie. ‘The sociology of arbitrage’: a comment on MacKenzie. Economy and Society,
33(2):239–254, 2004.
J. M. Harrison and D. M. Kreps. Martingales and arbitrage in multiperiod securities
markets. Journal of Economic Theory, 20:381–401, 1979.
J. M. Harrison and S. R. Pliska. Martingales and stochastic integrals in the theory of
continuous trading. Stochastic Processes and their Applications, 11:215–260, 1981.
J. M. Harrison and S. R. Pliska. A stochastic calculus model of continuous trading:
complete markets. Stochastic Processes and their Applications, 15:313–316, 1983.
E. G. Haugh and N. N. Taleb. Why we have never used the Black–Scholes–Merton option
pricing formula. 2009.
M. G. Kendall. On the reconciliation of theories of probability. Biometrika, 36(1/2):
101–116, 1949.
J. M. Keynes. The collected writings of John Maynard Keynes. Vol. 8 : Treatise on
probability. Macmillian, 1972.
D. MacKenzie. An equation and its worlds: Bricolage, exemplars, disunity and
performativity in financial economics. Social Studies of Science, 33(6):831–868, 2003.
D. MacKenzie. An Engine, Not a Camera: How Financial Models Shape Markets. The
MIT Press, 2008.
M. S. Mahoney. The Mathematical Career of Pierre de Fermat, 1601–1665. Princeton University Press, 1994.
M. S. Mahoney. The Mathematical Career of Pierre de Fermat, 1601–1665. Princeton University Press, 1994.
B. Mandelbrot. Forecasts of future prices, unbiased markets and ”martingale” models.
The Journal of Business, 39(1, Supplement on Security Prices):242–255, 1966.
R. C. Merton. Theory of rational option pricing. The Bell Journal of Economics and
Management Science, 4(1):141–183, 1973.
H. Miyazaki. Between arbitrage and speculation: an economy of belief and doubt. History
of Political Economy, 36(3):369–415, 2007.
H.L. Reitz. Review of Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung. Bulletin of the
American Mathematical Society, 40(7):522–523, 1934.
W. Schachermayer. Die Uberprufung der Finanzierbarkeit der Gewinnbeteiligung.
Mitteilungen der Aktuarvereinigung Osterreichs, 2:13–30, 1984.